We should see the nations of the world as distinct and beautiful flowers in the garden of culture. It is the love of this uniqueness of each nation which should inspire all lovers of national integrity to fight against the globalized monoculture that the globalist Imperium wishes to impose…

In his essay “Towards Patriotism: An Alternative to Nationalism,” Mark Malvasi takes issue with my response to his earlier essay, “History as Tragedy and Farce: The Rise of Nationalism.” In my response to that earlier essay, I had set out to provide “a coherent definition of Nationalism.” Mr. Malvasi seems to have a problem not only with my definition of Nationalism but with the very idea of a definition itself. “I must confess at the outset,” he writes, “to a certain antipathy for definitions,” adding that “there is an elusive, even illusory, quality to definitions.”

Let’s begin, therefore, with a defence of definition.

Mr. Malvasi makes his argument, or communicates his viewpoint, with the use of words. Without words, he could communicate nothing. He can only communicate in this way because he knows that he and his readers share the same understanding of the words he uses. His words have definite meanings because we all possess definitions for them. This is true, regardless of the fact that words, and therefore definitions, can be slippery. They can sometimes slip through our grasp and can in this sense be “elusive,” in which case it is all the more imperative that we endeavor to grasp them firmly. This understanding of words and their definitions was certainly grasped by Dr. Johnson, whom Mr. Malvasi cites rather bizarrely as one who supports his own “antipathy for definitions.” The mind boggles that the world’s greatest lexicographer can be enlisted in Mr. Malvasi’s war on definition. It must be suspected, therefore, that Mr. Malvasi has misunderstood Dr. Johnson’s meaning.

Definition is most important in cases where words appear to have multiple meanings, or when they are “slippery.” If a word such as “love” means something entirely different to the Christian, who sees it as a rational and self-sacrificial choice, than it does to the romantic relativist, who sees it as merely an ultimately irrational feeling, or to the hard-nosed materialist, who sees it as nothing but chemical wiring in the brain, it is imperative that the different meanings are defined before the word can be used meaningfully. A failure to do so will lead inevitably and inexorably to the sort of radical relativism which deconstructs language until the very existence of objective meaning is denied. These are the shifting sands of relativist nonsense upon which no meaningful dialectic or dialogue can be founded.

Shunning such nonsense, and leaving aside Mr. Malvasi’s “antipathy for definitions,” let’s return to the definition of “nationalism.” In his earlier essay, Mr. Malvasi had defined nationalism in terms of the political movements which led to the foundation of modern nation states. In my response, I wrote that “it could be argued that the sort of nationalism which Mr. Malvasi criticizes in his essay was not really nationalism at all but was, in fact, a form of imperialism.” My argument was based upon the fact that the inherent dynamic in nineteenth-century nationalism was a movement towards the “unification” of previously non-existent “nations” through the destruction of the political autonomy of the previously existing regions. This was a manifestation of the progressive centralization of power into the hands of fewer and bigger governments which has since metamorphosed into the globalism which, ironically, threatens to destroy the very nations which this same centralizing dynamic had established.

The alternative to this progressive centralization of power, its antithesis and antidote, is the political dynamic of progressive decentralization. In this sense, I see the political sovereignty of existing nation-states as a bulwark against the centralizing tendency of globalism, hence the definition of nationalism that I employed:  Nationalism is a belief in the political sovereignty of nations. Its antonym is internationalism, a belief in the absence or minimizing of the political sovereignty of nations. It can be seen that all forms of imperialism are essentially internationalist and that, therefore, nationalism in the sense in which I have defined it, can never be imperialist.

As with the definition of “love”, alluded to above, it seems, therefore, that we need to distinguish between the historical “nationalism,” of which Mr. Malvasi writes, which was a manifestation of the centralization or “unification” of power into fewer hands, and the contemporary “nationalism” to which I refer, which serves to prevent or obstruct the centralization or “unification” of power into fewer globalist hands. They are not the same thing (indeed they are opposites) and it is perilous to conflate them.

Although it’s not my primary intention to critique Mr. Malvasi’s appraisal of nineteenth-century nationalism, it is not possible to allow his sympathetic portrayal of the secular fundamentalist regime of Otto von Bismarck to go unchallenged. During the so-called kulturkampf from 1871 until 1890, Catholics were persecuted, suffered legal disabilities, and were imprisoned or exiled, all in the name of national pride and “unity”—a unity that excluded a third of the nation’s population! It is also frankly absurd that Mr. Malvasi appears to believe that the secular fundamentalism of Bismarck’s regime did not lay the foundations for Hitler’s.

Although Mr. Malvasi was gracious enough to concede that I had “ably demonstrated” that it was “too facile to insist that all forms of nationalism are the same,” he claimed to be “hard pressed to know what form of nationalism” I had in mind when I wrote that “genuine nationalism seeks the preservation or restoration of authentic national and regional cultures and the preservation or restoration of the strong local government necessary to defend them. It is intrinsically anti-imperialist, intrinsically local, intrinsically decentralist in its being and its raison d’être.”

Since Mr. Malvasi is “hard pressed” to understand the sort of nationalism to which I refer, I will offer him some examples. One could point to the Scottish or Welsh Nationalists who seek autonomy for their nations from what they perceive as the imperialism of the United Kingdom. Historically one could point to the Irish Nationalists who sought Home Rule from Britain. I would also add that I consider myself an English Nationalist, as distinct from a British Nationalist, and, as such, would welcome Scottish and Welsh independence, should the peoples of those nations vote for it. One could also mention the nations that gained their freedom from the Soviet Union, and one might hope that one day the nations of Europe will gain their freedom from the imperialism of the European Union.

And so to “patriotism.”

For all his disdain for definitions, Mr. Malvasi is at pains to insist that “the differences between ‘nationalism’ and ‘patriotism’ are fundamental.” He then bases his discussion of these fundamental differences on what might be called an Orwellian understanding of each word, quoting Orwell’s condemnation of nationalism and his praise for patriotism. According to Orwell, patriotism emphasizes tradition and is often conservative and even reactionary. According to Mr. Malvasi’s paraphrasing of Orwell, it is “deeply rooted in the soil of a specific place and the history of a particular people. It is introverted and defensive.” Orwell wrote that a patriot is proud of his country’s way of life, “which he considers to be the best in the world but which he has no wish to force…upon other people.” Here, and speaking as one who considers himself a patriot, I would object that Orwell’s patronizing patriotism, which presumes a supercilious superiority over other countries, is not something to which any true patriot should subscribe. I love my own country but I wouldn’t dream of thinking that other people’s countries are inferior to mine. We should see the nations of the world as distinct and beautiful flowers in the garden of culture, each offering something unique to the whole bella vista of humanity’s cultural panorama. It is the love of this uniqueness of each nation which should inspire all lovers of national integrity to fight against the globalized monoculture that the globalist Imperium wishes to impose.

“In important respects,” writes Mr. Malvasi, “Orwell’s patriotism was outside of, and beyond, politics. Nor was it primarily intellectual. Orwell’s England was not an idea or a concept. His version of patriotism found its significance and enjoyed its fullest expression, in social custom and practice—that is, in the concrete ways in which and by which a people live.” Absolutely, Mr. Malvasi. It was this patriotic desire which led the English people to vote for Brexit, indicating that the continuum of “social custom and practice” and “the concrete ways in which and by which a people live” can only survive if patriotism is protected by politics. A failure to defend one’s way of life will lead to one’s way of life being destroyed. In this sense, patriotism might exist “outside of, and beyond, politics” but it cannot survive without political protection. And this is why patriotism needs good, healthy, contemporary nationalism, as distinct from the imperialism masquerading as nationalism which Mr. Malvasi and Orwell both correctly despise. “A patriot,” writes Mr. Malvasi, “can love his own country without hating, or seeking to dominate, another.” On this Mr. Malvasi and I can agree wholeheartedly. We only differ insofar as I believe that a nationalist can also love his own country without, hating, or seeking to dominate, another.

Books by Joseph Pearce may be found in The Imaginative Conservative BookstoreThe Imaginative Conservative applies the principle of appreciation to the discussion of culture and politics—we approach dialogue with magnanimity rather than with mere civility. Will you help us remain a refreshing oasis in the increasingly contentious arena of modern discourse? Please consider donating now.

All comments are moderated and must be civil, concise, and constructive to the conversation. Comments that are critical of an essay may be approved, but comments containing ad hominem criticism of the author will not be published. Also, comments containing web links or block quotations are unlikely to be approved. Keep in mind that essays represent the opinions of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of The Imaginative Conservative or its editor or publisher.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email